Well-ordering principle

From HandWiki
Short description: Statement that all sets of positive numbers contains a least element


In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty set of positive integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of positive integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which x precedes y if and only if y is either x or the sum of x and some positive integer (other orderings include the ordering 2,4,6,...; and 1,3,5,...).

The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers {,2,1,0,1,2,3,} contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Properties

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:

  • In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
  • Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set A of natural numbers has an infimum, say a*. We can now find an integer n* such that a* lies in the half-open interval (n*1,n*], and can then show that we must have a*=n*, and n* in A.
  • In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers n such that "{0,,n} is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.

In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set S, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method[citation needed] and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).

Example applications

The well-ordering principle can be used in the following proofs.

Prime factorization

Theorem: Every integer greater than one can be factored as a product of primes. This theorem constitutes part of the Prime Factorization Theorem.

Proof (by well-ordering principle). Let C be the set of all integers greater than one that cannot be factored as a product of primes. We show that C is empty.

Assume for the sake of contradiction that C is not empty. Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element nC; n cannot be prime since a prime number itself is considered a length-one product of primes. By the definition of non-prime numbers, n has factors a,b, where a,b are integers greater than one and less than n. Since a,b<n, they are not in C as n is the smallest element of C. So, a,b can be factored as products of primes, where a=p1p2...pk and b=q1q2...ql, meaning that n=p1p2...pkq1q2...ql, a factor of primes. This contradicts the assumption that nC, so the assumption that C is nonempty must be false.[2]

Integer summation

Theorem: 1+2+3+...+n=n(n+1)2 for all positive integers n.

Proof. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that the above theorem is false. Then, there exists a non-empty set of positive integers C={n1+2+3+...+nn(n+1)2}. By the well-ordering principle, C has a minimum element c such that when n=c, the equation is false, but true for all positive integers less than c. The equation is true for n=1, so c>1; c1 is a positive integer less than c, so the equation holds for c1 as it is not in C. Therefore, 1+2+3+...+(c1)=(c1)c21+2+3+...+(c1)+c=(c1)c2+c=c2c2+2c2=c2+c2=c(c+1)2 which shows that the equation holds for c, a contradiction. So, the equation must hold for all positive integers.[2]

References

  1. Apostol, Tom (1976). Introduction to Analytic Number Theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 13. ISBN 0-387-90163-9. https://archive.org/details/introductiontoan00apos_0/page/13. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 Lehman, Eric; Meyer, Albert R; Leighton, F Tom. Mathematics for Computer Science. https://courses.csail.mit.edu/6.042/spring17/mcs.pdf. Retrieved 2 May 2023. 

cs:Princip dobrého uspořádání