Conservative extension

From HandWiki

In mathematical logic, a conservative extension is a supertheory of a theory which is often convenient for proving theorems, but proves no new theorems about the language of the original theory. Similarly, a non-conservative extension is a supertheory which is not conservative, and can prove more theorems than the original. More formally stated, a theory T2 is a (proof theoretic) conservative extension of a theory T1 if every theorem of T1 is a theorem of T2, and any theorem of T2 in the language of T1 is already a theorem of T1.

More generally, if Γ is a set of formulas in the common language of T1 and T2, then T2 is Γ-conservative over T1 if every formula from Γ provable in T2 is also provable in T1.

Note that a conservative extension of a consistent theory is consistent. If it were not, then by the principle of explosion, every formula in the language of T2 would be a theorem of T2, so every formula in the language of T1 would be a theorem of T1, so T1 would not be consistent. Hence, conservative extensions do not bear the risk of introducing new inconsistencies. This can also be seen as a methodology for writing and structuring large theories: start with a theory, T0, that is known (or assumed) to be consistent, and successively build conservative extensions T1, T2, ... of it.

Recently, conservative extensions have been used for defining a notion of module for ontologies: if an ontology is formalized as a logical theory, a subtheory is a module if the whole ontology is a conservative extension of the subtheory.

An extension which is not conservative may be called a proper extension.

Examples

Model-theoretic conservative extension

With model-theoretic means, a stronger notion is obtained: an extension T2 of a theory T1 is model-theoretically conservative if T1T2 and every model of T1 can be expanded to a model of T2. Each model-theoretic conservative extension also is a (proof-theoretic) conservative extension in the above sense.[3] The model theoretic notion has the advantage over the proof theoretic one that it does not depend so much on the language at hand; on the other hand, it is usually harder to establish model theoretic conservativity.

See also

References

  1. 1.0 1.1 S. G. Simpson, R. L. Smith, "Factorization of polynomials and Σ10-induction" (1986). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 31 (p.305)
  2. Fernando Ferreira, A Simple Proof of Parsons' Theorem. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, Vol.46, No.1, 2005.
  3. Hodges, Wilfrid (1997). A shorter model theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 58 exercise 8. ISBN 978-0-521-58713-6